the French flag
book cover

Summary: Critique of Pure Reason

The Critique of Pure Reason is Kant’s fundamental work, published in 1781, in which he analyses the various faculties of the mind to establish that our knowledge cannot extend beyond the limits of experience.

He sets out to demonstrate that metaphysics cannot constitute a true science and must give way to belief.



The Critique of Pure Reason is a difficult work. In fact, its difficulty arises mainly from the fact that the Preface is filled with allusions to the content of the book (from the Introduction to the final chapter), which remain incomprehensible until one has read the entire work. Yet, due to these numerous obscurities, the Preface often discourages readers from proceeding further.

The simplest approach is to begin with the Introduction, as it contains essential definitions and distinctions. One can return to the Preface once these have been grasped, at which point its allusions will become clearer.


This work seeks to answer the question: What can we know? This is a fundamental question in epistemology, examined in particular by Descartes, Locke, and Hume. Do our ideas correspond to something real, or are they mere fabrications? Is the external world truly as we perceive and conceive it to be? Are our theories about the world correct?


To understand a philosopher, it is often helpful to identify the thinker against whom they are primarily arguing.


Kant opposes Hume and, more generally, empiricism, according to his own account.

For empiricism, the mind is like a kind of tabula rasa (a term used by Locke), originally containing no ideas. One might also describe it as a blank slate. Experience is the source of our ideas and knowledge. For example, it is by seeing the colour red that the idea of ‘red’ enters our mind. Similarly, it is by experiencing the feeling of anger within ourselves that the idea of ‘anger’ takes shape in our mind.

Ideas are thus formed through experience, either external (that of the world around us) or internal (when the mind experiences certain things within us, as in the case of anger).

Empiricists therefore reject the theory of innate ideas, which holds that we are born with certain pre-formed ideas, such as the idea of God.


Kant opposes the empiricist doctrine. He challenges the notion that the mind, the intellect—or rather, to use his own terminology, the understanding—is a neutral medium in which ideas simply come to be formed.


Kant’s idea is that the understanding has a particular form. This means that it does not simply receive ideas from external things without altering them, as it would if it were a neutral tabula rasa. In fact, for something to become an object of knowledge and take shape as an idea, it must be modified in such a way as to conform to the form of the understanding.

A useful analogy is that of a glass: for a liquid to enter the glass, it must take on its shape, whatever that may be. Similarly, for an idea to form within our understanding, it must adapt to the form of our understanding.


What is this form? It consists of a set of a priori concepts, or categories. These are fundamental concepts upon which the very functioning of our understanding depends. Here are a few examples (we will later see the full list): quality, quantity, causality, and so on.

Thus, for an object to be constituted as an object within our intellect, it must have a certain quantity. And indeed, we see that all our ideas of objects correspond to something singular or multiple—in short, something possessing a certain quantity.

We can intuitively see that the idea of causality is more fundamental than, for example, the idea of metal. The former is an a priori concept of the understanding, whereas the latter is an empirical concept. One could imagine being deprived of the idea of metal, but the idea of causality is essential to our intellect.

What does the term a priori concept mean? A priori means that which precedes experience and is independent of it. This contrasts with a posteriori, which refers to that which is derived from experience. A posteriori and empirical are synonymous, just as pure and a priori are synonymous (a pure concept is one that is entirely a priori).

We can now understand why these fundamental concepts of the understanding are a priori concepts. Since they constitute the very form of the understanding, they are not formed in us through experience. On the contrary, it is these concepts that enable us to think about any object of experience and even to constitute objects as objects of experience.

1 The references for the quotations are available in the book Kant: Guided Reading